Mathematics Asked by Zhen Lin on November 19, 2021
It is extremely well-known that Zorn’s lemma is a theorem of ZFC. My interest is in a certain finitely-axiomatisable fragment of ZFC, sometimes called RZC (restricted Zermelo with choice) or ZBQC. The axioms of RZC are the following:
Adrian Mathias also defines an extension of RZC, called MAC (Mac Lane set theory), by adding the transitive containment axiom:
(Apparently RZC and MAC are equiconsistent.)
Question. Is Zorn’s lemma a theorem of RZC? If not, is it a theorem of MAC?
It is reasonably clear that well-founded induction is valid in RZC, but without the axiom of replacement it is not at all obvious to me whether Hartogs numbers exist. ($V_{omega + omega}$ is a model of RZC, but the only von Neumann ordinals in $V_{omega + omega}$ are precisely those below $omega + omega$, even though it has uncountable well-ordered sets.) Once we know that there are sufficiently large well-ordered sets, it seems to me that the usual proof of Zorn’s lemma will go through in RZC.
Motivation. One can build a model of RZC out of any model of ETCS (elementary theory of the category of sets) and ETCS can be interpreted in any model of RZC. What I really want to know is whether ETCS proves that, say, every vector space has a basis, and it seems like a good first step would be to establish the claim for RZC.
Actually, one does not need to use any ordinals to prove Zorn's lemma in RZC!
Theorem: Every non-empty partial order $(S,<)$ in which every non-empty chain has an upper bound has a maximal element.
Proof: We shall work under the assumption that the claim is false. First let $F$ be a choice-function that maps each chain $C$ in $(S,<)$ to a strict upper bound for $C$ in $S$. (This is the only use of AC in this proof, and also shows that it suffices for $S$ to be well-orderable in absence of AC.) We say that $T$ is a tower iff $T$ is a well-ordered chain in $(S,<)$ and $∀x{∈}T ( x = F(T_{<x}) )$. Note that any two towers $T,U$ agree, meaning that one is a subchain of the other, since otherwise $T{∖}U$ and $U{∖}T$ are both non-empty and disjoint and so letting $m = min_<(T{∖}U)$ and $n = min_<(U{∖}T)$ we would obtain $m = F(T_{<m}) = F(U_{<n}) = n$ and hence a contradiction. Now let $V$ be the union of all the towers, and observe by the above note that it is a tower too, but that $V∪{F(V)}$ is a taller tower, contradicting the definition of $V$.
Answered by user21820 on November 19, 2021
The argument proposed by Zhen Lin works once one knows that $Y$ (as defined there) is well-ordered by the "obvious" relation $prec$, namely that one equivalence class is smaller than another if some (equivalently every) element of the first class embeds as a proper initial segment in some (equivalently every) element of the second class. Zhen Lin leaves this issue unsettled when $mathbb N$ doesn't exist, but even when $mathbb N$ does exist, the proposed argument doesn't work. The reason is that it uses the equivalence between "well-ordered" and "has no decreasing $omega$-sequence"; this equivalence is not provable in the absence of the axiom of choice (more precisely, it needs the principle of dependent choice (DC), which is one of the weak forms of AC). So here's a proof, without $mathbb N$ and without DC, that $Y$ is well-ordered.
Let $Z$ be a nonempty subset of $Y$; we need to show that $Z$ has a smallest element. Consider any element $[R]$ of $Z$. By the notation $[R]$ I mean the isomorphism class of a well-ordering $Rinmathcal F$ (still using the notation of Zhen Lin's answer). If $[R]$ is the smallest element of $Z$, we're done, so assume it is not. This means that $Z$ has other elements $[S]$ whose elements $S$ are embeddable as initial segments of $R$. Each such initial segment is, since $R$ is a well-order, of the form ${x:xRa}$ for some $a$ in the field of $R$. Let $Q$ be the set of those elements $a$ that arise in this way, i.e., the set of those $a$ in the field of $R$ such that the initial segment consisting of the $R$-predecessors of $a$ (ordered by the restriction of $R$) is in one of the isomorphism classes in $Z$. Because $R$ is well-ordered, $Q$ has a smallest element $b$. It is then easy to check that the isomorphism class of ${x:xRb}$ (again ordered by the restriction of $R$) is the smallest element of $Z$.
Answered by Andreas Blass on November 19, 2021
This reformulation of the construction Hartogs number seems to work:
Lemma (Hartogs). If $X$ is a set, then there is a well-ordered set $Y$ for which there is no injection $Y to X$.
Proof. Let $overline{X}$ be any set containing $X$ as a proper subset. Let $mathcal{F}$ be the set of all well-orderings of subsets of $overline{X}$; this can be constructed using power sets, cartesian products, and $Delta_0$-separation, and let $mathcal{F}_0$ be the subset of $mathcal{F}$ consisting of well-orderings of $X$. Let $Y$ be the set of isomorphism classes in $mathcal{F}$; this can be constructed using power sets, function sets, and $Delta_0$-separation. $Y$ has an obvious linear order (using induction over well-ordered sets), and in fact it is well-ordered.
If $mathbb{N}$ (in the sense of a set for which mathematical induction is valid) exists, we proceed by supposing $Y$ is not well-ordered: then by mathematical induction we could produce an $mathbb{N}$-indexed strictly descending sequence $$y_0 > y_1 > y_2 > cdots$$ in $Y$, but the sequence $y_1 > y_2 > cdots$ can then be embedded in a representative of the class $y_0$, implying $y_0$ is not an isomorphism class of well-orderings – which is a contradiction. [Does this need choice? Embeddings of one well-ordered set as an initial segment of another are unique if they exist, so I'm inclined to believe this is choice-free...]
If $mathbb{N}$ does not exist, then [...?]
Once we have shown $Y$ is well-ordered, it is easy to prove that every member of $mathcal{F}_0$ embeds as a proper initial segment of $Y$. A standard argument then shows there is no injection $Y to X$: indeed, if there were, then $Y$ would embed as a proper initial segment of itself – an absurdity. ◼
The standard proof of Zorn's lemma now goes through without problems:
Lemma (Zorn). If $X$ is a partially-ordered set such that every well-ordered chain in $X$ has an upper bound in $X$, then $X$ has a maximal element.
Proof. Let $mathcal{G}$ be the set of well-ordered chains in $X$; this can be constructed using power sets and $Delta_0$-separation. Using the axiom of choice, we may choose once and for all an upper bound for each well-ordered chain in $X$, so that we obtain a function $u : mathcal{G} to X$ such that $z < u(Z)$ for all $Z$ in $mathcal{G}$ and all $z$ in $Z$. [I think the axiom of choice is only needed to construct $u$ and nowhere else.]
Let $Y$ be a well-ordered set so large that there is no injection $Y to X$, and suppose for a contradiction that $X$ has no maximal elements. We define an injective monotone function $f : Y to X$ by recursion:
This produces the desired contradiction. ◼
Answered by Zhen Lin on November 19, 2021
Get help from others!
Recent Questions
Recent Answers
© 2024 TransWikia.com. All rights reserved. Sites we Love: PCI Database, UKBizDB, Menu Kuliner, Sharing RPP