Mathematics Asked on November 12, 2021
I’ve been trying to understand the recursion theorem for quite a while now and I still don’t think I understand it 100%, I’ve checked multiple books and pdfs and I’ve noticed that this theorem is often stated in two different ways
Let $A$ be a set, $a ∈ A$, and $r : N × A → A$ any function. Then there exists a function
$f : N → A$ such that (i) $f(0) = a$, and (ii) $f(n + 1) = r(n, f(n))$ for all $n ∈ N$.
Let $X$ be a set, $a ∈ X$, and $f : X → X$.
Then there exists a function $u : ω → X$ such that $u(0) = a$ and $u(n^
+) = f(u(n))$
for all $n ∈ ω$
Why sometimes $N×A$ is used as domain for the function $r$ in the first case and $f$ in the second case, and sometimes just $X$ is used? What is the difference?
Another answer has already explained why both versions are equivalent. However, I want to add that there is a third version that is actually preferable if you want to be able to use the recursion theorem easily.
This version allows you to define the value of the recursive function $h$ on an input $k$ based on not just $k$ but also all the values of the recursive function on inputs less than $k$, since this information can all be obtained from $h↾k$. (In case you are not familiar with $ω$, treat it as the naturals such that $k = { j : j∈ω ∧ j<k }$ for every $k∈ω$.)
You should be able to see how version (2) can be used to prove version (3), by applying it to $R$ and then taking the union.
~ ~ ~
I also want to point out a significantly stronger version of the recursion theorem:
This version cannot be proven without using the replacement schema in ZFC, because it can be used to construct $V_{ω+ω}$, which is a model of ZFC minus replacement. Replacement also does not immediately furnish a suitable codomain for the desired $h$, since the "$∀x$" in "$∀x ∃!y ( Q(x,y) )$" is an unbounded quantifier. So to prove (3) we need to do something else. One easy way is to prove $∀k{∈}ω ∃!g ( FD(g,k^+) ∧ g(0)=c ∧ ∀j{∈}k ( Q(g(j),g(j^+)) ) )$ where $FD(g,d)$ is a predicate that says "$g$ is a function with domain $d$", which would require using the well-ordering of $ω$, and then use replacement to get $∃F ∀k{∈}ω ∃!g{∈}F ( FD(g,k^+) ∧ g(0)=c ∧ ∀j{∈}k ( Q(g(j),g(j^+)) ) )$, and finally construct $h = bigcup { g : g∈F ∧ k∈ω ∧ FD(g,k^+) ∧ g(0)=c ∧ ∀j{∈}k ( Q(g(j),g(j^+)) ) }$ and prove that $h$ is a function witnessing the claim.
Answered by user21820 on November 12, 2021
At first glance, it seems that the first variant is more general (to compute the next term, you can use the previous term - but also the current index). More formally, if the first version holds and you are given $X,a,f$ as in the second, then apply the first to $A:=X$, $r(n,a):=f(a)$. Then the $f$ (in the notation of 1) is a valid $u$ (in the notation of 2).
Interestingly, however, we can also infer the first variant from the second: Assume we are given $A,a,r$ as in the first. Let $X=Ntimes A$ and define $fcolon Xto X$ as $f(langle n,arangle) = langle n^+,r(n,a)rangle$. Then the existing $u$, composed with the projection $Ntimes Ato A$ is a valid solution for the first variant.
Answered by Hagen von Eitzen on November 12, 2021
Get help from others!
Recent Questions
Recent Answers
© 2024 TransWikia.com. All rights reserved. Sites we Love: PCI Database, UKBizDB, Menu Kuliner, Sharing RPP